(To go to the second part, click here.)
This paper takes a plunge into the classic debate between prominent legal philosophers H.L.A. Hart and Lon L. Fuller, which now marks its 55th year of publication in Harvard Law Review. Published in 1958, Hart’s and Fuller’s lectures in the Review have been stimulating intellectual exchanges between legal positivist and natural law schools.
In the paragraphs that follow, I would like to demonstrate the development of arguments delivered by Hart and Fuller in their respective articles. The topics include the separation of law and morals, the imperative theory of law, legal interpretation, law under the Nazi regime, fidelity to law, etc. All these topics sum up in one question: How should one define the relationship between law and morals? These two schools of law take contrasting positions.
Hart and the Separation of Law and Morals
Hart opens the lecture with a statement made by contemporary voices, that there exists a ‘point of intersection between law and morals’; in other words, ‘what is and what ought to be are somehow indissolubly fused or inseparable’. This is the subject of the lecture: to question such statements and demonstrate that they are either right or wrong.
Classic Legal Positivism
As a first step, Hart seeks the history of legal understanding. Here he introduces two most prominent philosophers in the English tradition of utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Austin (1790–1859). He praised them for having criticised natural-law philosophers due to the latter’s reluctance in distinguishing law as it is from law as it ought to be—a simple but vital move that would simply assure maximum clarity in legal understanding.
This paper takes a plunge into the classic debate between prominent legal philosophers H.L.A. Hart and Lon L. Fuller, which now marks its 55th year of publication in Harvard Law Review. Published in 1958, Hart’s and Fuller’s lectures in the Review have been stimulating intellectual exchanges between legal positivist and natural law schools.
In the paragraphs that follow, I would like to demonstrate the development of arguments delivered by Hart and Fuller in their respective articles. The topics include the separation of law and morals, the imperative theory of law, legal interpretation, law under the Nazi regime, fidelity to law, etc. All these topics sum up in one question: How should one define the relationship between law and morals? These two schools of law take contrasting positions.
Hart and the Separation of Law and Morals
H.L.A. Hart (1907-1992) |
Hart opens the lecture with a statement made by contemporary voices, that there exists a ‘point of intersection between law and morals’; in other words, ‘what is and what ought to be are somehow indissolubly fused or inseparable’. This is the subject of the lecture: to question such statements and demonstrate that they are either right or wrong.
In order to achieve this end, Hart takes the
following steps. First, he clarifies
the positivist understanding of law and morality as proposed by classic legal
positivists. Second, he examines the
imperative theory of law and demonstrates its weaknesses. Third, he criticises formalist interpretation of cases vis-à-vis
legal realism by introducing the concepts of umbra and penumbra. Fourth, he tackles criticisms against legal
positivism in the wake of the collapse of Nazi’s regime. All these steps are
taken to show that there is no necessary relationship between law and morality.
As a first step, Hart seeks the history of legal understanding. Here he introduces two most prominent philosophers in the English tradition of utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Austin (1790–1859). He praised them for having criticised natural-law philosophers due to the latter’s reluctance in distinguishing law as it is from law as it ought to be—a simple but vital move that would simply assure maximum clarity in legal understanding.
However, Hart recognises as well that
nowadays such separation has been no longer popular, perceived as ‘superficial
and wrong’. It is accused of blinding ‘men to the nature of law and its roots
in social life’, of intellectually misleading and practically corrupting. The
term ‘Legal Positivism’ has then been understood pejoratively.
Even among these classic legal philosophers,
Hart finds some differences. Austin, in spite of supporting the distinction
between law as it is and law as it ought to be, still believed in God’s
commands, which were thought to be the fundamental principles of morality. On
the other hand, Bentham defined morality by making reference only to
utilitarian principles.
Differences notwithstanding, they both wanted
people to understand the consequences of morally bad laws and the character of
a legal order’s authority. Otherwise, as Bentham described, the confusion
between law and morals would result in two positions of error:
- The anarchist, who does not acknowledge the law: ‘This ought not to be the law, therefore it is not and I am free to disregard it.’ This group of people may dissolve law and its authority in their conceptions of what law ought to be.
- The reactionary, who equates the law with morality: ‘This is the law, therefore it is what it ought to be.’ This group of people may replace morality with the existing law and thus avoid any criticism, since such law is claimed to be in line with morality.
- There exists ‘the intersection of law and morals’. Law and morals have influenced one another over the course of history. Austin even called it ‘frequent coincidence’ of positive law and morality, which, he argued, explained the confusion between what law is and what law ought to be.
- The legal system may explicitly include moral principles in its provisions and the law may bind courts to take account of what they think just or best prior to making judgement.
- If a rule violated morality, then it must not be a rule of law—a position otherwise taken by the anarchist.
- If a rule was morally desirable, then it must be a rule of law—a position otherwise taken by the reactionary.
Tackling the First Criticism: Imperative Theory of Law
Hart now pays attention to criticisms of the separation of law and morals. He points out three different doctrines of which the utilitarian tradition in jurisprudence consists:
Hart now pays attention to criticisms of the separation of law and morals. He points out three different doctrines of which the utilitarian tradition in jurisprudence consists:
- The separation of law and morals: there is no necessary relationship between law and morals
- Analytical study of legal concepts: a study of the meaning of legal vocabulary
- Imperative theory of law: law is essentially a command
Hart now zeros in on the third doctrine,
which has been frequently criticised. The imperative
theory of law as proposed by Austin has three key ideas:
- Command: ‘an expression by one person of the desire that another person should do or abstain from some action’, accompanied by
- Sanction: ‘a threat of punishment, which is likely to follow disobedience’, and commanded by
- Sovereign: ‘a person or a group of persons who are in receipt of habitual obedience from most of the society but pay no such obedience to others’.
- Legislature, or even electorate, whose membership changes periodically, can impossibly be considered a group of persons habitually obeyed by society; only a long-lived monarch can receive such obedience.
- Law-making procedures, with which legislators must comply in order to make law, can impossibly be expressed as commands habitually obeyed. These procedures are ‘fundamental accepted rules’ that lie at the root of a legal system, whose social and official acceptance is the ‘key to the science of jurisprudence’.
- The criminal law is certainly a command since it requires individuals to do something or to refrain from doing something regardless of their will. This law says, ‘Do this whether you wish it or not.’
- But contracts, wills, trusts, and similar rules are not a command since they are more of enabling individuals to create structures of rights and duties within a certain legal framework. This type of law says, ‘If you wish to do this, here is the way to do it.’
Tackling the Second Criticism
Legal interpretation in the judicial process
is now the subject of attention. Hart calls it the problems of the penumbra, which take place in debatable cases, in
contrast to settled meaning. An
example is given as follows: No vehicles
may enter public parks. While an automobile is what the term ‘vehicle’
refers to, a wide range of other objects may cause doubts; does the rule apply
to bicycles, roller skates, toy automobiles, or even aeroplanes? Here the
standard instance (e.g. automobile) causing no doubt is called a core of
settled meaning, whereas those which cannot be taken in certainty are called
‘penumbra’.
If the penumbra of uncertainty must include
all rules of law, then mere logical
deduction can impossibly apply to specific cases in the penumbral area.
This is then a point of, as some people claim, ‘intersection between law and
morals’; moral judgement is thought to be the factor enabling an individual to
make sound judgement in a specific case, a domain in which deductive reasoning
alone is not enough. However, Hart denies such an easy resort.
Hart admits that formalism is often accused of ignoring the problems of penumbra. At
the level of legal theorist, critics argue that s/he has mistakenly seen legal
decision as an act relying solely on deduction from premises, thereby not
involving the judges’ practical choices at all. Judges are then merely robots
who ‘find’, never ‘make’, law.
However, Hart argues that a judge does have to apply a rule to a concrete
case—a position in line with realism.
Why? Because logic can only give a hypothetical conclusion from a certain
interpretation of a certain term; it does not prescribe the interpretation. It
says nothing about how to classify particular things, which is precisely the
very core of a judicial decision. And such decision in the penumbral area, Hart
says further, should take account of social values and consequences arising
therefrom.
Therefore, can one draw a conclusion that the
utilitarian insistence on the separation between law and morals is wrong, because
deciding cases in an automatic way is wrong whereas deciding cases by reference
to social purposes is right? No, says Hart. He argues that a drastic
restatement must be made: The aims, the social policies, and purposes, of which
the judges should take account in order for their decisions to be rational, are
themselves part of the law. This way, a legal decision in the penumbral area,
albeit unnecessarily guided by moral considerations, is always made in the
light of social aims. Therefore, the
error of formalism does not automatically falsify the utilitarian insistence on
the separation between law and morals.
Furthermore, Hart believes that such
separation should not be dropped because of two reasons.
- Laws are always incomplete. General proposition can never decide concrete cases. That is why penumbral cases must be decided rationally by reference to social aims—or, in a word, discretion.
- The hard core of settled meaning is always important, however fine its borderline is with penumbral cases. If one softens the distinction between law and morals, then, they are suggesting that all legal questions are simply in the penumbral area, with no central element of law—a condition that is obviously not true.
Hart tells a story of Gustav Radbruch, a
German thinker who previously supported the positivist doctrine until the
advent of Nazi regime, after which he renounced the doctrine of the separation
of law and morals and insisted on joining these two aspects.
In the wake of the war, Geman courts changed
drastically, applying Radbruch’s conception of law as containing in itself
moral principles. As a result, numerous people were charged of committing
crimes previously not illegal under the Nazi law. The latter was also declared
invalid in the name of the principle of morality. He also recounts a case in
1949, in which a wife was prosecuted for an offence of depriving his husband of
his freedom. The wife made use of the Nazi regime to bring her husband, who had
made insulting remarks about Hitler, to the Nazi court. After the war, the wife
was brought to trial under the new Criminal Code enacted in 1871. The court
declared that the wife was guilty and the Nazi statute that she had used to
defend herself was annulled because it was considered against the sense of
justice of all human beings.
Responding to the
aforementioned cases, Hart argues that the Utilitarians would say that ‘the
Nazi law may be law but too evil to be obeyed’.
No comments:
Post a Comment
I'd like to hear from you. Put your comments below!